Can there be a ‘cosmetic’ psychopharmacology? prozac unplugged: the search for an ontologically distinct cosmetic psychopharmacology
Blackwell Science, LtdOxford, UKNUPNursing Philosophy1466-7681Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 200562131143Original articleProzac UnpluggedPamela Bjorklund
Can there be a ‘cosmetic’ psychopharmacology? Prozac unplugged: the search for an ontologically distinctcosmetic psychopharmacology
Pamela Bjorklund RN MS CS PMHNP Assistant Professor, Department of Nursing, The College of St. Scholastica, Duluth, MN, USAAbstract
‘Cosmetic psychopharmacology’ is a term coined by Peter Kramer inhis 1993 best-seller, Listening to Prozac. It has come to refer to the useof psychoactive substances to effect changes in function for conditionsthat are either normal or subclinical variants. In this paper, I ask:What distinguishes an existential ailment from clinical depression, oreither of those from normal depressed mood, melancholic tempera-ment, dysthymia or other depressive disorders? Can we reliably distin-guish one from the other? Are the boundaries of illness and disorderreally so distinct? If not, how can we know that treatment of ‘depres-sion’ with Prozac in any given instance constitutes a cosmetic asopposed to, say, a medical or clinical use of psychopharmacology – adistinction that seems to turn on our ability to clearly differentiate theclinical from the cosmetic. If we cannot reliably distinguish betweensuch conditions, can we even have a cosmetic psychopharmacologythat is not a form of malpractice, broadly speaking? What if weunplugged Prozac from all the amplitude and hype that resulted inListening to Prozac becoming an instant best-seller and simply askedwhether or not we can clearly distinguish an appropriate cosmetic useof Prozac for ‘depression’ from an inappropriate cosmetic use ofProzac, and both of those from Prozac’s appropriate clinical, that is,non-cosmetic uses? If we cannot make these distinctions, perhaps itis too early to say there can be such a thing as a cosmeticpsychopharmacology.
cosmetic psychopharmacology, Prozac, depression,
Correspondence: Pamela Bjorklund, Department of Nursing, The College of St. Scholastica, 1200 Kenwood Avenue, Duluth,
Minnesota 55811-4199, USA. Tel.: +218 723 66 24; fax: +218 723 64 72; e-mail: pbjorklu@css.edu
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
his much-praised, and much-maligned,1 1993 best-
Introduction
seller, Listening to Prozac. It is his ‘mnemonic’ for
If a patient is not tearful, inappropriately guilty, having trou-
what he observed as Prozac’s effect in transforming
ble concentrating, losing sleep, losing weight, thinking about
the selves of even non-depressed individuals – leaving
death or suicide – in short, if she is not clinically depressed
them ‘better than well’ and more ‘socially attractive’
– yet she responds to an antidepressant, then what exactly
(Kramer, 1993; p. xvi). In Elliott’s (2004) words,
is that antidepressant treating? A personality disorder?
‘[Kramer] was referring to the way psychoactive
Unhappiness? Existential dread? . . . What if Prozac does, in
drugs could be used not just to treat illnesses but to
fact, treat existential ailments? What if it really does make
improve a person’s psychic well-being . . . [to move] a
a person feel less alienated, less fearful of death, more at
person from one normal state to another’ (p. 1). To
home in the world, more certain about how to live a life? Is
summarize, the term has come to refer to the use of
psychoactive substances like Prozac to effect changes
The Last Physician: Walker Percy & the Moral Life of Med-
in function for conditions that are either normal or
subclinical variants (Sperry & Prosen, 1998). These
are conditions, in other words, that are either clearly
Carl Elliott asks a good question: What, indeed,
not medical conditions – rather, are spiritual or exis-
would be wrong with that? Apart from issues of mal-
tential conditions, or perhaps are merely part of the
practice perhaps, at least in some cases, what is wrong
human condition – or that might turn out to be med-
with prescribing an antidepressant for someone who
ical but are still too subtle to detect as existing med-
is not depressed but rather is merely – as if this were
ical conditions, or that might turn out to be medical
not difficult enough – alienated, fearful of death, ill
once a sufficiently advanced biomedicine can locate
at ease in the world and uncertain of the purpose in
life? Certainly, some of what is wrong is that this sort
What might be wrong with prescribing Prozac, or
of ‘existential ailment’, whether spiritual, rooted in
any of the other new- or old-generation antidepres-
biology, or both, is part of the human condition. To
sants,2 for an existential ailment is an important and
exist as a human being is to have the capacity to
intriguing philosophical question – and it begs many
question the meaning and purpose of life, and to
know and fear the inevitability of death. This is not
1Elliott (2000) calls it a ‘splendid book’ (p. 8) while Rothman
disease or disorder. This is a reasonable, natural,
(1994) writes: ‘Were Listening to Prozac a package insert, it
expectable, normal, if you will, response to shifts in
would never get FDA approval . . . To the extent that Kramer is
frameworks of meaning, or to problematic social con-
typical of his generation of physicians, it is plain that trusting the
ditions in troubled times: ‘Some kinds of responses to
medical profession to be strict gatekeepers before therapies,
the world are reasonable even when they are
new or otherwise, is foolhardy. Anybody who expects physicians
disturbing . . . . For all the good that antidepressants
to save us from ourselves, or from the worst imaginable abuses
do, there remains the nagging suspicion that many of
of twenty-first century medical interventions . . . had better start
the things they treat are in fact a perfectly sensible
searching for alternatives’ (p. 34).
response to the strange times in which we live’
2To treat depressive disorders, we now have a long list of new-
and old-generation antidepressant medications, including the
Here and elsewhere, Elliott (1999a, 1999b, 2000,
selective serotonin reuptake inhibitors (SSRIs), the norepineph-
2003, 2004), who is a bioethicist, expresses his con-
rine dopamine reuptake inhibitors (NDRIs), the selective
cerns about the medicalization of human unhappi-
serotonin norepinephrine reuptake inhibitors (SNRIs), the sero-
ness, an insidious development implicit even in
tonin-2 antagonists/reuptake inhibitors (SARIs), the noradren-
Elliott’s use of the term ‘existential ailment’, and
ergic/specific serotonergic antidepressants (NaSSAs), the non-
about the implications of a cosmetic psychopharma-
selective cyclic antidepressants (including tricyclics, tetracyclics
cology to treat it. ‘Cosmetic psychopharmacology’ is
and dibenzoxazepine), the irreversible monoamine oxidase
a term coined by Peter Kramer in the introduction to
inhibitors (MAOIs) and the reversible inhibitor of MAO-A
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
others. First of all, no one seriously questions the
So, here are the questions that concern me: What
appropriateness of treating clinical depression with
distinguishes an existential ailment from clinical
Prozac. ‘Major depression can be lethal’, writes
depression – or either of those from depressed mood,
Elliott (1999a). ‘Up to 15 percent of patients who
alienation, melancholia, dysthymia, or other depres-
have major depression commit suicide. For such peo-
sive disorders? (This is not so simple a question as it
ple, antidepressants can be lifesaving’. Obviously, he
first seems.) Can we reliably distinguish one from the
is not concerned about the use of antidepressants by
other? Are the boundaries of illness and disorder
those people. What worries him about Prozac is not
really so distinct? If not, how can we know that treat-
its use to treat ‘illnesses’ per se, but rather the possi-
ment of ‘depression’ with Prozac in any given instance
bility that the ‘ills’ for which Prozac is so often pre-
constitutes a cosmetic as opposed to, say, a medical
scribed are ‘part and parcel of the lonely, forgetful,
or clinical use of psychopharmacology? In other
unbearably sad place where we live’ (Elliott, 2000; p.
words, how would we know a cosmetic psychophar-
8). If so, then something important is lost when we
macology when we saw one? Is it anything other than
try to medicate away such distress. It is to this Wyatt-
inappropriate prescriptive practice, meaning it falls
Brown (1999) refers when he notes (in Inherited
outside the boundaries of the current accepted psy-
Depression, Medicine, and Illness in Walker Percy’sArt) that ‘pain and ordeal had their indispensable
Whether an antidepressant is used clinically or cos-
uses’ (p. 116) and that ‘Dostoevsky taught . . . that
metically seems to turn on our ability to clearly dif-
[existential] “suffering is an evil, yet . . . through the
ferentiate the clinical from the cosmetic, that is, to
ordeal of suffering one gets these strange benefits of
differentiate normal depressed mood and the existen-
lucidity, of seeing things afresh” ’ (Percy 1985; p.
tial ailments that can produce such moods – along
116). It is fair and accurate to say that Prozac has
with, say, bad marriages and stressful jobs – not only
both legitimate and illegitimate uses. Determining
from melancholic temperament but also from clinical
which is which and what is cosmesis and what is med-
depression, dysthymia and the depressed mood that
ical treatment (or is cosmesis now the same as
accompanies so many other appropriately diagnosed
medical treatment?) has become quite problematic,
psychiatric disorders.3 If we cannot reliably distin-
at least for some philosophers and psychiatrists.
guish between such conditions, and thereby deter-
Clearly, in order to say that a cosmetic psychophar-
mine whether an antidepressant is medically
macology exists, or is even a legitimate possibility,
indicated or not, can we even have a cosmetic psy-
those who use Prozac to treat disease and disorder
chopharmacology – defined as a psychopharmacol-
must be able to distinguish between the ‘ills’ that are
ogy for normal variants that uses Prozac to, e.g. ‘help
part and parcel of our unbearably sad world – for
which the prescription of Prozac then becomes a
3Depressed mood can be symptomatic, e.g. of the personality
cosmetic psychopharmacology – and the medical
disorders, post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD), other anxiety
‘illness’ called clinical depression for which the pre-
disorders, schizoaffective disorder, bipolar illness and substance
scription of Prozac is simply an instance of applied
abuse. In addition, it is hugely stressful to be mentally ill. Almost
any psychiatric disorder can be accompanied by depressed
mood – not to mention of course, that major depression can co-
(RIMA). This does not include an equally long list of mood-
occur with almost any other psychiatric diagnosis. Sorting all this
stabilizing medication often used in conjunction with antide-
out can be extremely complex. More often than we care to
pressants to treat bipolar depression (See Bezchlibnyk-Butler &
admit, there is no way to know in any given clinical instance
Jeffries, 2004). ‘Prozac’ is used in this paper to denote any anti-
whether treatment with an antidepressant is appropriate or not
depressant available to treat a depressive ‘condition’, but partic-
– except to try it and see whether a patient’s symptoms remit.
ularly those new-generation, low side-effect and high safety
Despite its considerable scientific advances, this may be one of
profile antidepressants, like Prozac, that ushered in the era of
psychiatry’s ugly, little secrets – that so much of what it does is
so-called ‘cosmetic psychopharmacology’.
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
frazzled parents cope with their kids or to make
chopharmacology cosmetic is that it moves a person
chronic loners stop fearing rejection’ (Nichols, 1994;
from ‘one normal, but unrewarded, state to another
p. 36) – that is anything other than psychiatric mal-
normal, better rewarded state’. However, if we can-
practice, broadly (not legally) speaking? Certainly, a
not unambiguously determine that the ‘unrewarded
psychiatric practitioner who is either inexperienced,
state’ from which one has been moved to that other
inept or disreputable can prescribe Prozac to some-
normal, ‘better rewarded state’ was, in fact, normal,
one who is not clinically depressed, who does not
how can we say this is an instance of cosmetic psy-
have any other diagnosable psychiatric disorder, or
chopharmacology? Where at least some mental states
whose mood is not depressed secondary to some
are concerned, including depressive states, it is occa-
other appropriately diagnosed psychiatric disorder –
sionally hard to distinguish between normal and
someone who simply wants, e.g. to be a better sales-
man (Sperry & Prosen, 1998; p. 55) or to more
successfully negotiate a union contract (Kramer,
Depression as normal mood or
1993; pp. 1–21). But what distinguishes a cosmetic
mood disorder?
psychopharmacology of this sort from inept or uneth-
ical psychiatric practice, or one lacking a scholarly
How are we to tell when a depressed state is normal
evidence base, which is not to say that if an evidence
or abnormal, healthy or unhealthy? In fact, what do
base existed for cosmetically treating ‘frazzled par-
we mean when we say someone is depressed or has
ents’ and ‘chronic loners’ with Prozac that such prac-
depression? It seems we must know what depression
is if we are to determine whether treatment of it with
What if we unplugged Prozac from all the ampli-
Prozac constitutes an instance of cosmetic psycho-
tude and hype that resulted in Listening to Prozac
pharmacology. Walter Glannon (2003a) notes that
becoming a blockbusting, instant best-seller,4 and that
most psychiatrists conceptualize depression, at least
continues to spawn debate, and simply asked whether
the more severe types that clearly constitute psychi-
or not we can clearly distinguish an appropriate cos-
atric illness, as a disorder of the mind arising from
metic use of Prozac for ‘depression’ from an inappro-
dysfunctions in the brain. He conceptualizes mind as
priate cosmetic use of Prozac, and both of those from
mental states generated and sustained by the brain
Prozac’s appropriate clinical, that is, non-cosmetic
and consisting in the capacity for cognitive states (e.g.
uses? If we cannot make these distinctions, perhaps
beliefs), conscious affective states (i.e. emotions) and
it is too early to say there can be such a thing as a
unconscious affective states (e.g. emotional memo-
cosmetic psychopharmacology. Peter Kramer (in
ries) that can arouse physiologic responses when trig-
Cooper, 1994) states that what makes cosmetic psy-
gered by external events. Although mental states
arise from brain physiology, they have a subjective
4Rothman (1994) writes that Listening to Prozac made the best-
quality and representational content – i.e. they are
seller lists ‘before it was so much as advertised or reviewed’ (p.
about something and are uniquely meaningful to the
34). In the Afterword to the 1997 edition, Kramer himself calls
person who experiences them – that cannot be
Listening to Prozac ‘more than a best-seller . . . the talk of the
explained in terms of the brain alone. Glannon thus
nation . . . a cultural icon’ (pp. 315–316): ‘Coverage spanned the
rejects the reductive materialism that undergirds so
media, including People, The Washington Post, Oprah, Good
much of biological psychiatry. This perspective
Morning America, and National Public Radio. At The New
assumes that consciousness and other forms of men-
Yorker, the book inspired one cartoon after another . . . The
tality are not simply caused by neurological processes
New York Times’ banner headline for its year-end summary of
in the brain; rather, they simply are neurological pro-
the arts was “Listening to 1993” ’ (pp. 315–316). The book made
cesses and therefore can be explained entirely in
Peter Kramer famous. It spawned something called ‘the Prozac
terms of the material or physical structures and func-
debate’ and dozens more books. Some of us are still engaged in
tions of the brain: ‘But insofar as our mental states
have a subjective phenomenology, and insofar as
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
their content involves features of the social and nat-
chemical deviation from normal physiology? Here,
ural environment, the mind cannot be explained
Prozac may or may not be a necessary intervention;
entirely in terms of the objective physical properties
but it clearly will not be sufficient.
of the brain and body’ (Glannon, 2003a; pp. 244–245).
Psychiatric drugs . . . only treat the symptoms of mental dis-
Depression, then, even the so-called clinical kind
orders; they do not treat the underlying causes . . . Given the
that Prozac can sometimes treat so well, is always
role that beliefs and emotions play in the sequence of events
more than reductive materialism would have it. It is
leading to depression, [Prozac] is insufficient because ther-
never simply biological, although it may be at least,
apeutic intervention must also take place at the mental level
or perhaps even mostly biological. Biological models
in themselves are inadequate to explain or treat com-
plex clinical phenomenology (Brendel, 2003a). It
Nevertheless, someone is suffering; Prozac might
sounds right to me that depression results not only
help. It will do no good to simply wait for social
from brain and body dysfunction but from mental
states as well. If so, factors external to the brain must
In locating depression and hence a cosmetic psy-
be considered to properly diagnose and treat the dis-
chopharmacology, Martin (2003) points out the
order – if it is a ‘disorder’ – because, again, the mental
importance of distinguishing between depression as a
states that figure in its aetiology have a subjective
mood and depression as a mood disorder. As a mood,
quality and representational content that reflect the
depression is a ‘state of low spirits, typically involving
social and natural environment (Glannon, 2003a). My
painful and low affect’ (p. 255). Of course, not all
depression is about something; and for me it may not
negative, low moods are depressions. It is ‘difficult to
be about, primarily at least, a deviation from normal
distinguish depression from grief, sadness, gloom, and
brain physiology. In other words, a biochemical dis-
a host of additional ways to feel down’ (p. 255).
turbance in neural transmission at the cellular level
Depressed persons are not always sick, and depressed
may be a factor in my depression, but so is the reality
moods are not all bad. They can be important in con-
that I live in a dangerous neighbourhood, have no job,
nection with questions of value, identity and even
no health insurance and no adequate childcare, do
moral insight: ‘[Depressed moods] involve negative
not have the resources to move to a better neighbour-
evaluations of ourselves, major events in our lives, life
hood, and increasingly feel helpless and worthless.
in its entirety, or the values that have been guiding
Perhaps I have come to believe my situation is hope-
us’ (p. 255) but can lead to a process of evaluation
less. As a single mother, underemployed, poorly
and revaluation that is essentially healthy.
dressed, with unmanicured hands and an old car, per-
In contrast, depression as a mood disorder is by
haps I feel unable to ‘approximate the currently fash-
definition pathologic, even though categories of
ionable ideal of the assertive, confident, resilient,
mood disorder fluctuate in the Diagnostic and Statis-
romantically satisfied producer and consumer’
tical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM) (American
(Parens, 2004; p. 27).5 Whether I have a diagnosable
Psychiatric Association, 2000) with every edition, and
mood disorder or not, might it not be normal, reason-
there are many additional states of suboptimal health
able and expectable to feel depressed under these
in which DSM criteria are only partly met, not to
circumstances? Would we then be using Prozac for
mention that the notion of pathology is itself under-
cosmetic purposes in medicating this ‘normal’ state?
stood in terms of values – ‘the values of health and,
Or, is it an ‘abnormal’ state, or only ‘abnormal’ if it
indirectly, moral values that define what is culturally
is, or might be accompanied by some kind of bio-
acceptable’ (Martin, 2003; p. 255). Clarity about def-
initions and distinctions is essential to gaining clarity
5Parens refers to Peter Kramer’s ‘abundant evidence’ (p. 27) in
about what is being assessed, explained and treated
Listening to Prozac that a cosmetic psychopharmacology can do
with Prozac by psychiatry and psychobiology. Such
exactly that – help people ‘better approximate’ currently fash-
clarity is important in determining what is unhealthy
or not, and in understanding the continuum between
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
health, suboptimal health and full-blown disorders.
1992). The biological psychiatrist defines disorder as
Our choice of terminology reflects our attitudes: ‘If
deviation from normal brain physiology (Olson,
we think of negative low moods as inherently unde-
2000). The philosopher may discuss disorder as a
sirable then we will tend to use the word depression
moral phenomenon – an essential suffering, the result
to connote sickness. If we discern value in many neg-
of which one’s life falls short of being a satisfactory
ative low moods we will be more likely to use the
or ‘good’ life in some non-biological sense – and
word depression to refer to a broad range of moods,
where the appropriate treatment is that species of
most of which are normal and some of which are
moral education called ‘psychotherapy’ (Matthews,
pathologic’ (p. 258). The term ‘cosmetic psychophar-
1999a, 1999b). The social scientist details disorder as
macology’ reflects a certain attitude, too. I am just not
(1) pure value concept; (2) whatever professionals
sure it is an attitude based on clear ontological dis-
treat; (3) statistical deviance; (4) biological disadvan-
tinctions between health and illness, depressed
tage; (5) distress or disability; or (6) harmful dysfunc-
mood and depressive disorder, or treatment and
tion. Wakefield prefers to conceptualize disorder as
the latter, where ‘harmful’ is a value system based on
social norms, and ‘dysfunction’ is a scientific term
referring to the failure of a mental mechanism to
Stretching the boundaries of illness
perform a natural function for which it was designed
The boundary between health and illness has never
by evolution. A mental disorder thus exists whenever
been distinct. In fact, social scientists cannot agree
a person’s internal mental – biological and psycholog-
that there is a boundary. Are health and illness dis-
ical – mechanisms fail to perform their functions as
crete categories, where you either meet criteria for a
designed by nature and this impinges harmfully on a
disease and thus are ill, or you do not and hence are
person’s well-being as defined by social values and
well? Or, do health and illness exist on a continuum
cultural meanings (Wakefield, 1992). The relevant
where the boundary between the two is not a line but
function at issue with either existential ailments or
an entire region with its own indistinct borders? Here,
depressive disorders is the exercise of effective
health slides into illness and illness slips back into
agency, which can be more or less impaired.
health almost imperceptibly such that you are not
When the impairment becomes severe, the psychiatrists’
clearly ill or well until you are closer to the extremes
DSM defines it as [an illness] based on sociocultural stan-
of the continuum. Keyes (2002) offers a third option
dards for normal or accepted behavior. But neither psychi-
and conceptualizes two separate continua for mental
atrists nor sociocultural standards are the final word. Insofar
health and mental illness. One can be more or less
as values are at stake, there is some legitimate domain
healthy at the same time that one is more or less ill.
within which individuals can reasonably make their own
Mental health is not merely the absence of mental
assessments, according to their own values, of [illness] and
illness, nor is it simply the presence of high levels of
subjective well-being. Rather, mental health concep-
tualized as a continuum between flourishing and lan-
In other words, my melancholy may be such that a
guishing is a complete state consisting of both the
psychiatrist sees a harmful dysfunction (depressive
relative presence of mental health symptoms and the
disorder) and recommends Prozac – or does not see
relative absence of mental illness symptoms. In this
a harmful dysfunction, empathizes with my existen-
schema, the absence of mental health (languishing) is
tial plight, and puts his prescription pad away – but
a risk factor for clinical depression (Keyes, 2002).
within certain limits I have some say. I am the one
To make matters more complex, social scientists,
who feels ill, well or something in between. I am the
medical doctors and philosophers cannot agree on
arbiter of my own suffering. I get to participate in the
exactly what illness, or disorder is, in part because
decision that my melancholy is disorder, or a normal
disorder lies on the boundary between the natural
response to disordered times. The question is: What
world and the constructed social world (Wakefield,
do we call it when neither I nor my psychiatrist is
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
sure that what I have, although I may feel decidedly
Categories of illness, especially mental illness, are
unwell, is an illness or a disorder, but we elect to try
constantly changing; and they tend to proliferate dra-
Prozac anyway? Is this cosmetic psychopharmacol-
matically once new treatments hit the market (Elliott,
ogy? And if we try Prozac, and it mitigates my suffer-
2004). The boundaries of any one of those shifting,
ing such that my overall functioning and the quality
proliferating, expanding categories remain elusive.
of my life on my own account are undeniably
They depend on time, space, cultural context, land-
improved, is this a cosmetic and not, or not also, a
scapes of care and the particularities of individual
clinical use of Prozac? (A more important question,
lives (say, any given patient’s moral framework and
perhaps, is whether we have done something
any particular prescriber’s educational background).
‘wrong’). Perhaps I may rightfully question whether
The elusive difference between treatment and
this is an instance of cosmetic psychopharmacology,
enhancement adds another layer of complexity: ‘Ill-
which by definition involves the use of Prozac to
ness and health, disability and difference, cure and
move me from one normal state to another normal
enhancement: it is a mistake to think there can be
state, because I hardly experienced the painful and
rigid distinctions here . . . [W]hat counts as an illness
debilitating state from which I was moved as
or a disability – or on the other hand, as normal
biological variation – will . . . depend on its cultural
New technologies like Prozac inevitably challenge
and historical location’ (Elliott, 1999b; p. 48). My
our definitions of health and illness, stretching their
point, exactly. If we cannot clearly distinguish health
margins and further blurring the boundaries between
from illness, disability from difference, cure from
normal variation (health) and pathology (illness)
enhancement – and the clinical from the cosmetic –
then how are we to recognize a cosmetic psychophar-
macology when we see one? How are we to know
Before various reproductive techniques . . . were developed,
when to use Prozac, and when to, say, call a priest?
infertility was simply a fact of nature; now that it can be
treated, it is a medical problem. Before the invention of the
lens, poor vision was simple a consequence of getting old. A case for Prozac – or something else?
Now it is something to be treated by a medical
This is how Sperry & Prosen (1998) pose the
Indeed, notes Elliott, doctors now treat an array of
Would you as a psychotherapist prescribe or refer for a
conditions that no one considers illnesses with
medication evaluation an individual who was not clinically
enhancement technologies6 by which no one is partic-
depressed nor even dysthymic, but requested Prozac – or
ularly troubled: ‘minoxidil for baldness, estrogen for
another selective serotonin reuptake inhibitor (SSRI) –
postmenopausal women, cosmetic surgery for people
because he believed it would make him a better salesman?
unhappy with their looks, acne treatment for self-
Would you prescribe or refer someone with dysthymic fea-
conscious teenagers’ (p. 26). And Prozac, he might as
tures who complained that her ‘depression was interfering
well add, for existential angst – and obsessive-com-
with my ability to meditate’? Or, would you prescribe or
pulsive behaviour, shyness, separation anxiety, sexual
refer for a medication evaluation someone with obvious
perversion, and a whole lot more that may or may not
symptoms of major depression that were in the moderate to
6Elliott (1999b) writes that the term enhancement technology
Let’s say that an expert psychiatric evaluation
‘generally refers to the use of medical technologies not to cure
results in no psychiatric diagnosis for the salesman
or control illness and disability, but to enhance human capacities
seeking to enhance his personal and professional per-
and characteristics . . . [including] the use of Prozac and other
sona with Prozac. He does not have a clinical, i.e.
antidepressants for shyness, a compulsive personality or low self
major depression and cannot be diagnosed with dys-
thymia, or minor depression; personality disorder,
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
where depression is a character trait or forms the core
a philosopher like Erik Parens, in an eloquent essay
of an essentially depressed self; or any other psychi-
on the use of Prozac for so-called cosmetic purposes
atric or medical condition for which depressed mood
(Parens, 2004), to pause and pointedly, rather
is so often adjunctive. He most certainly does not
emphatically insert into the text: ‘Please note:
have a melancholic temperament and suffers no more
Kramer [referring to the author of Listening to
than occasional, normal depressed mood when he
Prozac] is not anxious about using Prozac to treat
fails to make an important sale. He does not see him-
clinical depression, nor am I’ (p. 22). There can be no
self as ‘ill’, nor does his caregiver, and he wants only
cosmetic psychopharmacology, it seems, at either
to boost his performance as a salesman. I feel confi-
dent in asserting that most expert psychiatric provid-
What about in the middle? Let’s take a look at the
ers would not endorse his request. Were a prescriber
person with dysthymic features who complains that
to offer Prozac, I suppose one could call that an
her depression is interfering with her capacity to
instance of cosmetic psychopharmacology, but it is
meditate. By virtue of those dysthymic features, this
most certainly also malpractice, broadly and poten-
person is likely to be chronically depressed, irritable,
tially even legally speaking. If this is cosmetic
fatigued and unable to enjoy life. She may or may not
psychopharmacology, then cosmetic psychopharma-
have sleep or appetite disturbances, but is likely to
cology cannot be a legitimate prescriptive practice. To
suffer from low self-esteem and perhaps even chronic
even call it cosmetic psychopharmacology is to confer
feelings of worthlessness and purposelessness. Let’s
some legitimacy to the practice in much the same way
suppose her dysthymic features have not reached the
calling a certain type of socially and medically accept-
diagnostic threshold for dysthymic disorder which,
able cosmetic surgery does. This is a legitimacy that it
according to the DSM, is a mood disorder – a type of
does not deserve. I am therefore disinclined to call
clinical depression although not clinical depression
this an instance of cosmetic psychopharmacology.
itself – for which there is a growing body of clinical
Let’s just call it inept or substandard care.
evidence that endorses antidepressants along with
Let’s turn to the person on the other side of Sperry
psychotherapy as a form of treatment. Inasmuch as
& Prosen’s (1998) dilemma. Here, an expert psychi-
we are treating a type of clinical depression, I would
atric evaluation results in a diagnosis of major depres-
not consider this to be an instance of cosmetic
sion for a young woman who has begun to wake up
psychopharmacology. To move even closer to the
at 4 am every morning feeling exhausted, despondent,
middle of this dilemma in search of a legitimate, or
nauseous with a visceral form of free-floating anxiety
shall I say, an ontologically distinct cosmetic psy-
and unable to shake off thoughts of death – her own,
chopharmacology, suppose the person with dysthy-
her mother’s, her pet’s, even the supposed deaths of
mic features, for whom meditation is an important
starving children the world over who cannot find
adaptive mechanism and may be one of her few
enough to eat. She is herself unable to eat and has
remaining pleasures, has a melancholic tempera-
lost 16 pounds in the last 3 weeks. Food tastes like
ment. She has always been prone to pessimism and
sawdust and its sensation in her stomach triggers
dark moods. It is part of who she is. It is normal for
severe anxiety about losing her tenuous hold on self-
her to be darkly pessimistic and depressed. However,
control and possibly committing suicide. Violent,
not being able to effectively meditate constitutes an
frightening images of death by gunshot wound to the
existential crisis for her in that it takes away part of
head intrude on her consciousness.7 Uncle!8 Enough
her purpose in living, and she experiences this exis-
said. No one can dispute the use of Prozac to treat
tential crisis as an illness, if only in the metaphysical
depression of this sort. It is the sort of case that causes
sense. Shall we give her Prozac, and if we do, does
this finally constitute a cosmetic use of psychophar-
7These details are taken from an actual case history.
macology? As Sperry & Prosen (1998) write, in all
8In some cultures, one cries ‘Uncle!’ when one’s arm has been
likelihood practitioners would split their vote on this
sufficiently twisted such that no further persuasion is needed.
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
ing in and of itself does not promote growth and self-
The problem of suffering
actualization, or transformation. Chronic depressed
Why can we not be certain that giving Prozac to the
mood and purposelessness often serve no useful pur-
person whose depressed mood is interfering with her
pose, especially when they might be eliminated with
ability to meditate constitutes an instance of cosmetic
pharmacotherapy, and most especially when our sub-
psychopharmacology? In a sense, we are back to our
ject experiences her chronic depressed mood and
beginning: if this is an existential ailment, what is
purposelessness as a form of suffering that she would
wrong with treating it with Prozac? However, this
gladly do without, even if there is a price to be paid.
time we ask the question while also wondering
What makes sense as an abstraction from an outside,
whether treating our meditator’s existential ailment
universal philosophical perspective looks ridiculous
with Prozac might not be an instance of cosmetic
when we try to say that the suffering of this particular
psychopharmacology. There are two important issues
subject – this real person in real time and space who
here: (1) the inevitability of divergent views on the
is having trouble in meditating and feels like she is
nature of suffering and its role in the human condi-
losing what little joy is left in her life – is suffering
tion and (2) our continuing uncertainty about the
that ultimately exists for her own good; is an essential
nature of psychiatric illness and the diagnostic system
part of the human condition, ignoring that it is her
human condition; and should not therefore be medi-
Sperry & Prosen (1998) discuss the first: they con-
cated away. In addition, the view that depression can
tend that the reason the vote would be split is that
be useful and desirable makes light of the fact that
the possibility of prescribing Prozac, not just in this
most forms of depression involve suffering that con-
but in each of the above instances, evokes different
sists of significant cognitive, affective and physical
views on human nature, especially different views on
dysfunction (Glannon, 2003b). Those forms of
the human condition and the role of suffering in the
depression therefore threaten rather than contribute
human condition. They find two very distinct perspec-
to meaningful life. Here, the legitimate purpose of
tives on human nature: ‘In one view, life is not meant
antidepressants is not to enhance cheerfulness or
to be a state of continuous happiness, contentment,
social desirability, but to restore people to a normal
and well-being. In fact, life is largely a struggle filled
level of functioning in their lives (Glannon, 2003b).
with pain, disappointment, grief, mourning, and sad-
It follows that where Prozac does this, it has served a
ness. In the other view, life can and should be as
legitimate clinical as opposed to cosmetic purpose.
fulfilling and actualizing as possible. Pain, anxiety,
There are at least two reasons why we cannot be
sorrow, and sadness are symptoms that can and
certain that giving Prozac to the person whose
should be alleviated with whatever means possible’
depressed mood is interfering with her ability to
(p. 56). On both accounts, suffering is an evil; how-
meditate either does or does not constitute an
ever, only on the latter account is it to be eliminated
instance of cosmetic psychopharmacology. First,
whenever, wherever and with whatever (moral)
assuming Prozac has worked in this case, in alleviat-
ing our subject’s suffering and improving her health,
On the first account, suffering is a ‘privileged’ state,
well-being and overall functioning, we have remedied
and treatment with Prozac for non-clinical (normal)
a harmful dysfunction as defined by Wakefield (1992).
and subclinical (abnormal but also undetectable) con-
We have treated a disorder, in other words. We have
ditions ‘robs life of its edifying potential for tragedy’
treated what is on our subject’s account, and perhaps
(Sperry & Rosen, 1998; p. 56). The experience of
also on our own account, an illness of sorts – again,
sadness, after all, is morally and developmentally nec-
if only in the metaphysical sense. The relief of suffer-
essary for human growth and self-actualization. This
ing by all appropriate, clinically sound means is a
is part of what is lost when Prozac is used for cosmetic
legitimate medical, or more broadly, clinical purpose
purposes to treat existential ailments that are part of
– as some of those who prescribe medications are not
the human condition. On the second account, suffer-
medical doctors but clinicians of another sort. Sec-
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
ond, we cannot be sure that this is an illness only in
disorders and thus creates a shared discourse despite
the metaphysical sense. Perhaps, it is also physiolog-
competing and incompatible theoretical and aetiolog-
ical. We can no longer assume that certain traits or
ical claims about the nature of mental disorder. With
states, such as irritability, pessimism, a certain dark-
a descriptive taxonomy like the DSM, illness catego-
ness of mood or nervous tension, reflect one’s basic
ries like major depression, dysthymia and melancho-
temperament and are merely part of the human con-
lia are identified and arranged into sets of observable
dition (Sperry & Prosen, 1998). In fact, if tempera-
psychological, physiological and behavioural sign and
ment is part of the human condition, it is part of the
symptom clusters, or syndromes (Radden, 2003).
biological human condition, for temperament is now
However, descriptivism comes in two guises: (1) onto-
known to be biologically based, at least partially her-
logical descriptivism, which is the view that categories
itable and present from birth (Watson, 2000). Perhaps
such as depression refer only to those observable
there is something biochemically, physiologically or
signs and symptoms and not to any underlying causal
genetically awry in our meditator’s processes of
framework and (2) causal descriptivism, which
chemical neurotransmission.9 Who can say that one’s
implies identifiable, underlying causes that give rise
irritability, pessimism, darkness of mood and the ner-
to the observable signs and symptoms. On the second
vous tension that prevents one from effectively med-
analysis, depression refers not only to the observable
itating is only metaphysical illness and not, or not
features of a depressive state but also to its underly-
also, physical disease – in which case it is harder to
label the case an instance of cosmetic psychopharma-
Once again, consider our dysthymic patient with
cology? This lands us squarely on top of the second
the melancholic temperament who is having difficulty
important issue identified in our search for an onto-
in meditating, and who resides in the middle of that
logically distinct cosmetic psychopharmacology,
region where an ontologically distinct cosmetic psy-
namely, our continuing uncertainty about the nature
chopharmacology is most likely to be found. Whether
of psychiatric illness and the diagnostic system that
dysthymia and melancholy can be equated for pur-
poses of treatment with clinical depression, for which
we have already determined Prozac is a legitimate
medical treatment and does not constitute an
Descriptivism, causal classification
instance of cosmetic psychopharmacology, depends
and drug cartography
on whether we adhere to a descriptivist or causal
According to Radden (2003), descriptivism denotes
ontology. To adopt descriptivism is to allow the simi-
the epistemological approach to classifying mental
larities and differences between the respective
disorders adopted by the American Psychiatric Asso-
descriptions of melancholy, dysthymia and major
ciation(2000) in its DSM. As the term suggests, it
depression to determine whether we are dealing with
describes the clinical features of various psychiatric
distinct conditions. To employ a causal ontology is to
set aside the descriptive differences and insist that
melancholy, dysthymia and depression are variants of
9The ‘biochemical deficiency’, e.g. serotonin deficiency, and ‘bio-
the same underlying condition despite differences in
chemical imbalance’ concepts so often used to explain the bio-
appearance (Radden, 2003). Whether we call giving
logical basis of depressive and other psychiatric disorders is no
Prozac to our melancholic meditator an instance of
longer considered adequate to describe either that which is
cosmetic psychopharmacology or not depends not
‘awry’ in the biologically-based psychiatric disorders, e.g. major
only on our view of human nature (Sperry & Prosen,
depression, bipolar disorder, schizophrenia, schizoaffective dis-
1998) but also on whether our ontological framework
order, obsessive-compulsive disorder and panic disorder – the
is descriptive or causal (Radden, 2003). Given that
list is growing – or that which psychopharmacologic agents
our current descriptivist methododology for psychiat-
‘treat’ or ‘correct’. (Stahl, 2000).
ric nosology does not in fact establish causes, it is
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
insufficient for determining what depression is. We
some evidence to think it does, at least Kramer10 and
can talk about what depression does, but not about
Elliott11 think so – then we might suppose all those
what it is (Hansen, 2003). As we are still unable
conditions constitute variants of the same biologic
to carefully determine the boundaries and shape
depressive spectrum ‘disorder’. Drug cartography
of depression, I am skeptical we can actually
appears to show in sharper relief than the science of
locate the boundaries and shape of a cosmetic
biological psychiatry currently warrants what causal
classification holds implicit. Nevertheless, if science
Radden (2003) discusses another interesting dis-
someday shows that all these conditions do in fact
tinction. She points out two widespread trends in cur-
consist in the same depressive spectrum disorder,
rent psychiatric classification: the first is the tendency
then there can be no sharp ontological distinctions, at
to attribute various forms of masked depression to
least in the middle of our prescriptive practice
those whose symptom picture is contrary to that por-
dilemma, between that which is said to be cosmetic
trayed in traditional (Western) classifications, for
psychopharmacology and that which is not.
example, Chinese women who do not feel depressed
but whose somatic symptoms are nevertheless taken
Conclusion: ‘a thousand cartwheels’
to indicate an underlying, masked depression, or men
in Western society whose acting out, substance abuse
In truth, I resonate with Elliott’s (1999a, 1999b, 2000,
and antisocial behaviour similarly are taken as
2003, 2004) exquisitely articulated concerns about the
expressive of an underlying, masked depressive dis-
medicalization of human unhappiness and the moral
order. Stimulated by rapid psychotropic drug devel-
implications of enhancement technologies. However,
opment, the second trend, called drug cartography,
I find cosmetic psychopharmacology – the term, the
constitutes ‘a remapping of psychiatric categories
concept and, to the degree it exists, the practice –
based not on traditional symptom clusters but on psy-
suspect for all the reasons articulated above, not the
chopharmacological effects’ (p. 38).
least of which is that the ‘conundrum’ of cosmetic
For example, Brendel (2003b) points to the work
psychopharmacology is ‘necessarily played out at a
of Hudson & Pope (1990) who, based on the response
historical moment, ours, when the categorization of
to certain antidepressant medications of eight medi-
alienation [and other depressive states] remains
cal/psychiatric conditions including major depression,
ambiguous’ (Kramer, 2000; p. 14). To some degree,
bulimia, panic disorder, obsessive-compulsive disor-
when we treat depression we simply do not know
der, attention deficit-hyperactivity disorder, cata-
what we are treating and therefore cannot say that
plexy, migraine and irritable bowel syndrome,
this treatment is merely or exclusively cosmetic.
argue that all these disorders may share a common
Andrew Solomon (2001) sums it up very well: ‘The
pathophysiologic abnormality and thus could be
shape and detail of depression have gone through a
understood as a single affective spectrum disorder.
Similarly, a variety of problems with impulse-control
10Listening to Prozac presents numerous instances of supposed
including overeating, gambling, paraphilias and vari-
personality change in response to treatment with Prozac.
ous patterns of alcohol and drug abuse are increas-
11In Pursued by Happiness and Beaten Senseless: Prozac and the
ingly regarded as obsessive-compulsive spectrum
American Dream, Elliott (2000) writes: ‘How many patients
disorders because Prozac effectively treats them
[take Prozac for alienation], and whether Prozac actually cures
(Radden, 2003). Thus, if Prozac, which acts at the
them, remains to be seen. It may be small in comparison to, say,
level of gene expression in chemical neurotransmis-
the number who use Prozac for depression. But I take it from
sion (Stahl, 2000), effectively treats – apart from
my psychiatric colleagues, from the case histories in Kramer’s
whether it should be used to treat – not only major
book and others, and from my many friends and acquaintances
depression but also dysthymia, melancholic personal-
who have used the drug, that whether it affects alienation is at
ity and existential alienation – and there is at least
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
thousand cartwheels, and the treatment of depression
ous associations of intellectual brilliance and later,
has alternated between the ridiculous and the
even genius – associations that are absent from
sublime . . . To understand the history of depression
today’s conception of depression, where one crite-
is to understand the invention of the human being as
rion is poverty of thought: ‘Melancholia was the dis-
we know and are him [or her]. Our Prozac-popping,
order of the man (of genius, of sensitivity, intellect,
cognitively focused, semialienated postmodernity is
and creativity), whereas today’s depression is both
only a stage in the ongoing understanding and control
apparently linked with women in epidemiological
fact and associated with the feminine in cultural
In voicing my suspicions about cosmetic psychop-
ideas. Depression’s gender link is the reverse of the
harmacology, I have asked far more questions than I
masculine and male associations of melancholia’ (p.
have attempted to answer. Yet, I must ask one more.
40). Is this perhaps why Kramer (2000), who started
To begin with, for whom is cosmesis most at issue?
it all, believes that ‘much of the discussion of cos-
Who, by and large, uses cosmetics? Who, for the
metic psychopharmacology is not about pharmacol-
most part, opts for cosmetic surgery? In Listening to
ogy at all – that is to say, not about the technology. Prozac, whose personalities and selves are being
Rather, “cosmetic pharmacology” is a stand-in for
transformed?12 For whom, then, does Kramer coin
worries about threats to melancholy’ (p. 16). I tend
the term ‘cosmetic psychopharmacology’? Who, in
to agree that ‘much of the discussion of cosmetic psy-
fact, reports depression in the greatest numbers?13
chopharmacology is not about pharmacology at all’,
Overwhelmingly, the answers to all these questions
but I do not think the issue is only ‘threats to melan-
are: women. To the degree it really exists, is cosmetic
choly’. There are other threats at large, and I cannot
psychopharmacology, then, a gendered concept, or
help but wonder what part is played in this debate by
gendered practice? Of course, it is beyond the scope
the fact that most of the people requesting or being
of this paper to address the question, but I will note
given Prozac for whatever purposes, cosmetic or clin-
this: Radden (2000, 2003) has examined the relation-
ship between today’s depression and the melancholia
of old. For hundreds of years, she writes, influenced
by Aristotle and almost every subsequent thinker
References
until the 18th century, melancholia carried glamor-
American Psychiatric Association (2000) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, 4th edn text revi-
12Kramer’s case studies almost exclusively involve women.
Bezchlibnyk-Buter K.Z. & Jeffries J.J. (2004) Clinical Hand-
DSM-IV-TR indicates that women are at significantly greater
book of Psychotropic Drugs, 14th edn. Hogrefe & Huber,
risk than men to develop major depression: ‘Studies indicate
that depressive episodes occur twice as frequently in women as
Brendel D.H. (2003a) Reductionism, eclecticism, and prag-
in men’ (p. 354); Kessler et al. (1994) document that women have
matism in psychiatry: the dialectic of clinical explana-
higher prevalence rates of affective disorder than men, as well
tion. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 28(5–6), 563– 580.
as ‘higher prevalences than men of both lifetime and 12-month
Brendel D.H. (2003b) A pragmatic consideration of the rela-
comorbidity of three or more [psychiatric] disorders’ (p. 12);
tion between depression and melancholia. Philosophy,
Dohrenwend et al. (1992) show that women, unlike men, have
Psychiatry and Psychology, 10(1), 53–55.
higher rates of depression at every level of socioeconomic status;
Cooper T. (1994) Prozac. The CQ Researcher Online. Avail-
and Mirowsky & Ross (1995) conclude that women not only
report greater distress, e.g. depressed mood, anger, sadness, anx-
cqresrre1994081900 [accessed 10 November 2004]. Docu-ment ID: cqresrre1994081900
iety, malaise and aches, but also genuinely experience more
Dohrenwend B.P., Levav I., Shrout P.E. et al.(1992) Socio-
distress than men, suggesting they bear a heavier burden of
economic status and psychiatric disorders: the causation-
hardship and constraint and thus revealing their relative disad-
selection issue. Science, 255, 946–952.
vantage in American society: ‘Overall, women experience dis-
Elliott C. (1999a) Prozac and the existential novel: two ther-
tress about 30% more often than men’ (p. 449).
apies. In: The Last Physician: Walker Percy and the Moral
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143 Life of Medicine (eds C. Elliott & J. Lantos), pp. 59–69.
illness. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 6(4), 299–
Elliott C. (1999b) A Philosophical Disease: Bioethics, Cul-
Matthews E. (1999b) Disordered minds: a response to the
ture and Identity. Routledge, London.
commentaries. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology,
Elliott C. (2000) Pursued by happiness and beaten senseless:
6(4), 321–322.
Prozac and the American dream. Hastings Center Report,
Mirowsky J. & Ross C.E. (1995) Sex differences in distress:
30(2), 7–12.
real or artifact? American Sociological Review, 60(3),
Elliott C. (2003) Better Than Well: American Medicine Meets the American Dream. W. W. Norton & Co., New
Nichols M. (1994) Questioning Prozac. Maclean’s, 107(21),
Elliott C. (2004) Introduction: Prozac as a way of life. In:
Olson D. (2000) Policy implications of the biological model
Prozac as a Way of Life (eds C. Elliott & T. Chambers),
of mental disorder. Nursing Ethics, 7(5), 412–424.
pp. 1–18. The University of North Carolina Press, Chapel
Parens E. (2004) Kramer’s anxiety. In: Prozac as a Way of Life (eds C. Elliott & T. Chambers), pp. 21–32. The Uni-
Glannon W. (2003a) Depression as a mind-body prob-
versity of North Carolina Press, Chapel Hill, NC.
lem. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 9(3), 243–
Percy W. (1985) Interview by Bradley R. Dewey. In: Con-versations with Walker Percy (eds L.A. Lawson & V.A.
Glannon W. (2003b) The psychology and physiology of
Kramer), p. 5. University Press of Mississippi, Jackson,
depression. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 9(3),
Radden J. (2000) The Nature of Melancholy: from Aristotle
Hansen J. (2003) Listening to people or listening to Prozac?
to Kristeva. Oxford University Press, New York, NY.
Another consideration of causal classifications. Philoso-
Radden J. (2003) Is this dame melancholy? Equating today’s
phy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 10(1), 57–62.
depression and past melancholia. Philosophy, Psychiatry
Hudson J.I., Pope H.G. Jr (1990) Affective spectrum disor-
and Psychology, 10(1), 37–52.
der: does antidepressant response identify a family of dis-
Rothman D.J. (1994) Shiny happy people. New Republic,
orders with a common pathophysiology? American 210(7), 34–38. Journal of Psychiatry, 147, 552–564.
Solomon A. (2001) The Noonday Demon: an Atlas of
Kessler R.C., McGonagle K.A., Zhao S. et al. (1994) Lifetime
Depression. Scribner, New York, NY.
and 12-month prevalence of DSM-III-R psychiatric disor-
Sperry L. & Prosen H. (1998) Contemporary ethical dilem-
ders in the United States. Archives of General Psychiatry,
mas in psychotherapy: cosmetic psychopharmacology and
51, 8–19.
managed care. American Journal of Psychotherapy, 52(1),
Keyes C. (2002) The mental health continuum: from lan-
guishing to flourishing in life. Journal of Health and Social
Stahl S.M. (2000) Essential Psychopharmacology: Neurosci-Behavior, 43(2), 207–222. entific Basis and Practical Applications, 2nd edn. Cam-
Kramer P. (1993, 1997) Listening to Prozac. Penguin Books,
bridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
Wakefield J.C. (1992) The concept of mental disorder: on
Kramer P. (2000) The valorization of sadness: alienation and
the boundary between biological facts and social values.
the melancholic temperament. Hastings Center Report,
American Psychologist, 47(3), 373–388. 30(2), 13–18.
Watson D. (2000) Mood and Temperament. The Guilford
Martin M.W. (1999) Depression: illness, insight, and iden-
tity. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 6(4), 271–
Wyatt-Brown B. (1999) Inherited depression, medicine, and
illness in Walker Percy’s art. In: The Last Physician:
Martin M.W. (2003) On the evolution of depression. Philos-Walker Percy and the Moral Life of Medicine (eds C.
ophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, 9(3), 255–259.
Elliott & J. Lantos), pp. 112–133. Duke University Press,
Matthews E. (1999a) Moral vision and the idea of mental
Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2005 Nursing Philosophy, 6, pp. 131–143
Lose 10 Pounds and Your Blood Pressure Medication Date updated: September 27, 2006 By Darin Painter Content provided by Revolution Health Group http://www.revolutionhealth.com/conditions/heart/high-blood-pressure/treat- overview/blood-pressure-medication Toprol, Inderal, Blocadren, Levatol — it's hard enough tough to pronounce these blood pressure medicines, let alone take them daily
Defining the spectrum of alleles that contribute to blood lipidconcentrations in humansSekar Ka, Kiran Musunuruand Marju Orho-MelanderaCardiovascular Disease Prevention Center, CardiologyDivision, Massachusetts General Hospital, Boston,Recently, genome-wide genetic screening of common DNA sequence variants hasMassachusetts, USA, bThe Johns Hopkins CiccaronePreventive Cardiology Center, Baltimo